Morality begins with biology, and specifically with the instincts
we
have evolved over eons to aid in our survival and reproduction.
For
human beings, there are three of these instincts:
One is based on kin selection, and it tells us that we should care
for
our closest relatives, especially our children. After all,
caring
for our relatives increases the likelihood of their survival and
reproduction, which in turn increases the likelihood of our genes
-
including the ones that lead us to care for our relatives - get
passed
on to future generations.
The second is the care we feel for our mates. As an animal
that
produces few offspring, requires a nine month gestation
culminating in
a precarious delivery and resulting in a
very vulnerable infant requiring years of care, we have evolved a
strong tendency to develop attachments to our mates. As
any parent can tell you, it takes at least two people to raise
children.
The third is sympathy. We, like many other animals, are
social
creatures, and, like so many prairie dogs, we are attuned to the
emotions and behaviors of our fellow humans. When one of us
is
frightened, the rest go into high alert; when one of us is angry,
we
can rouse the ire of an entire mob; when one of us is laughing,
others
begin to laugh as well - even when they don't get the joke.
Of these three, sympathy is the weakest. In the animal
world,
there are
always "cheaters," animals of the same species who take advantage
of
others who instinctually aid each other. In the human world,
we
have a great many examples of these cheaters, whom we often label
"sociopaths." Also, the tendency to sympathy depends a great
deal
on social learning. It needs to be nourished by
example. In any family where sympathy is lacking, any
instinctual
tendency a child may have can easily be destroyed by abuse or
neglect,
or just self-centered parenting.
As human beings, we have evolved a rather large brain, and one
that is
capable of learning a great many things, not least of which is
language. The ability to learn allows much quicker
adaptation to
environmental change than evolution, and so tends to "drive out"
much
of the hardwiring that animals come supplied with. Certainly
we
still have instincts, but they can be over-written with social
learning
far most easily than in, say, cats and dogs.
A community that has survived and expanded for many decades or
centuries is one which has provided its members with patterns of
thinking, feeling, and behaving that permit that survival.
We
could call these patterns memes, or stick to older words such as
beliefs and techniques - it doesn't matter. Among the
patterns
that appear to work well for most societies are ones that
encourage
extending the range of the instincts of sympathy and love of
family to
all members of the community, rather than just close
relations.
Traditions of mutual respect, obedience to authority, cooperation,
and
so on, are good examples. These traditions make it less
likely
that community members waste their energies on internal conflicts
and
use it instead on productive activities, community defense, and,
possibly, expansion at the expense of other communities.
The Hebrews of the Old Testament are a great example of a
community
whose beliefs allowed them to prosper. But when the Bible
says we
should love our neighbor, it clearly meant our neighbor literally,
our
fellow Hebrew, and not, say, Egyptians or Assyrians or Canaanites,
as evidenced by all the rather vicious warfare of the day.
Being
good to one's enemy, someone who is not a member of our "tribe,"
is a
rather novel concept, one, in fact, that makes its appearance only
among
the Jews of Hellenistic times (after Alexander the Great).
After
all, any community that has
the belief that they should be nice even to aggressors, is a
community
that usually doesn't last long and takes that pleasant belief down
with
it.
Although the idea of universal respect had been promoted earlier,
notably by Buddha, Jesus, and Greek philosophers, the movement
that
would be most influential in actualizing the idea would not come
until
the Enlightenment. I believe that this was because it was
only
then that we had essentially filled the planet. Nations and
Empires were
butted up against each other with no room to wiggle. It had
become clear that, if we were to be happy, we could no longer stop
at
making nice with our literal neighbors or our fellow
tribe-mates.
We had to make nice with other nations, other cultures, perhaps
even
everybody! The difficulty here, of course, is that you need
to
convince people to move beyond their instinctive love of family,
beyond
the social indoctrination provided by their tribe, towards
accepting
the fundamental sanity of universal respect.
The great value of this biosocial view of morality is that it
removes
the issue from religious and philosophical debate and places it
squarely in the realm of the pragmatic. Without denying the
inherently subjective nature of our goals as human beings, we may
be
able to agree that one reasonable goal is the maximizing of
happiness. The question is then how do we educate people to
understand that it is in all our best interests to nurture our
innate
tendencies toward compassion.
Traditionally, psychology has avoided studying anything that is loaded with value judgements. There is a degree of difficulty involved in trying to be unbiased about things that involve terms like "good" and "bad!" So, one of the most significant aspects of human life - morality - has had to wait quite a while before anyone in psychology dared to touch it! But Lawrence Kohlberg wanted to study morality, and did so using some of the most interesting (if controversial) techniques. Basically, he would ask children and adults to try to solve moral dilemmas contained in little stories, and to do so outloud so he could follow their reasoning. It wasn't the specific answers to the dilemmas that interested him, but rather how the person got to his or her answer.
One of the most famous of these stories concerned a man named Heinz. His wife was dying of a disease that could be cured if he could get a certain medicine. When he asked the pharmacist, he was told that he could get the medicine, but only at a very high price - one that Heinz could not possibly afford. So the next evening, Heinz broke into the pharmacy and stole the drug to save his wife's life. Was Heinz right or wrong to steal the drug?
There are simple reasons why Heinz should or should not have stolen the drug, and there are very sophisticated reasons, and reasons in between. After looking at hundreds of interviews concerning this and several other stories, Kohlberg outlined three broad levels and six more specific stages of moral development.
Level I: Pre-conventional morality. While infants are essentially amoral, very young children are moral in a rather primitive way described by the two preconventional stages.
Stage 1. We can call this the reward and punishment stage. Good or bad depends on the physical consequences: Does the action lead to punishment or reward? This stage is based simply on one's own pain and pleasure, and doesn't take others into account.Level II: Conventional morality. By the time children enter elementary school, they are usually capable of conventional morality, although they may often slip back into preconventional morality on occasion. But this level is called conventional for a very good reason: It is also the level that most adults find themselves in most of the time!Stage 2. This we can call the exchange stage. In this stage, there is increased recognition that others have their own interests and should be taken into account. Those interests are still understood in a very concrete fashion, and the child deals with others in terms of simple exchange or reciprocity: "I'll scratch your back if you scratch mine." Children in this stage are very concerned with what's fair, but are not concerned with real justice.
Stage 3. This stage is often called the good boy/good girl stage. The child tries to live up to the expectations of others, and to seek their approval. Now the concern includes motives or intentions, and concepts such as loyalty, trust, and gratitude are understood. Children in this stage often adhere to a concrete version of the Golden Rule, although it is limited to the people they actually deal with on a day-to-day basis.Level III: Post-conventional morality. Some adolescents and adults go a step further and rise above moralities based on authority to ones based on reason.Stage 4. This is called the law-and-order stage. Children now take the point of view that includes the social system as a whole. The rules of the society are the bases for right and wrong, and doing one's duty and showing respect for authority are important.
Stage 5. The social contract stage means being aware of the degree to which much of so-called morality is relative to the individual and to the social group they belong to, and that only a very few fundamental values are universal. The person at this level sees morality as a matter of entering into a rational contract with one's fellow human beings to be kind to each other, respect authority, and follow laws to the extent that they respect and promote those universal values. Social contract morality often involves a utilitarian approach, where the relative value of an act is determined by "the greatest good for the greatest number."Stage 6. This stage is referred to as the stage of universal principles. At this point, the person makes a personal commitment to universal principles of equal rights and respect, and social contract takes a clear back-seat: If there is a conflict between a social law or custom and universal principles, the universal principles take precedence.
I can't leave Kohlberg without mentioning his younger colleague
at
Harvard, Carol
Gilligan.
Kohlberg's early research was done at a
boy's school. Later, when girls became part of the research
population, the girls were regularly rated as lower in the stages
than
boys of the same age. Upon investigating further, Gilligan
found
that it was the way in which the girl's expressed themselves that
led
the raters to place them in earlier stages, and that, under
review,
their answers were often at the same or even higher levels than
the
boys. It seems that girls (and women) tend to view moral
situations in terms of relationships and commitment, rather than
in
terms of rules and regulations. That made them appear to be
functioning at level 2 or 3, when in fact they were expressing
something closer to level 5.
Gilligan went a bit further with this than I am comfortable with,
by
suggesting that the differences in moral thinking between males
and
females is tied to genetics, and that female forms of morality are
essentially superior to male forms.
Another psychologist unafraid to tackle morality was Urie Bronfenbrenner. He is famous for his studies of children and schools in different cultures. He outlines five moral orientations:
1. Self-oriented morality. This is analogous to Kohlberg's pre-conventional morality. Basically, the child is only interested in self-gratification and only considers others to the extent that they can help him get what he wants, or hinder him.The next three orientations are all forms of what Kohlberg called conventional morality:
2. Authority-oriented morality. Here, the child, or adult, basically accepts the decrees of authority figures, from parents up to heads of state and religion, as defining of good and bad.The last orientation is analogous to Kohlberg's post-conventional level:3. Peer-oriented morality. This is basically a morality of conformity, where right and wrong is determined not by authority but by one's peers. In western society, this kind of morality is frequently found among adolescents, as well as many adults.
4. Collective-oriented morality. In this orientation, the standing goals of the group to which the child or adult belongs over-ride individual interests. Duty to one's group or society is paramount.
5. Objectively oriented morality. By objectively, Bronfenbrenner means universal principles that are objective in the sense that they do not depend on the whims of individuals or social groups, but have a reality all their own.Bronfenbrenner noted that while 1 is found among children (and some adults) in all cultures, 6 is found in relatively few people in any culture. The differences between 2, 3, and 4 are more a matter of culture than of development. Many cultures promote strict obedience to authority figures. One can see this in some middle eastern cultures, where the word of the religious authorities is law. In many western cultures, conformity to one's peers is a powerful force. And in others still, such as some Asian cultures, the welfare of the group is considered far more important than that of the individual.
Bronfenbrenner also talks about how we get movement from one orientation to another. The movement from 1 to 2, 3, or 4 involves participation in the family and other social structures, where concern for others begins to take precedent over concern for oneself.
Movement from 2, 3, or 4 to 5 occurs when a person is exposed to a number of different moral systems which at least partially conflict with each other, a situation he calls moral pluralism. This forces the person to begin to think about what might lie beneath all the variation, and lead him or her to consider ultimate moral principles.
On the other hand, sometimes people slide back down to the lowest orientation when they suffer from the disintegration of social structures, as in war and other social disasters. This can force a person's attentions back onto their own needs, and cause them to begin ignoring the welfare of larger social groupings.
The first perspective I call the egocentric perspective. I used to call it the autistic perspective, but since I originally wrote about it, the word "autistic" has come to be associated strongly with the disorders of the autistic spectrum. Nevertheless, the egocentric perspective on morality is the perspective held by infants, very young children, perhaps autistic children, and perhaps some psychotic adults. The person taking this perspective sees the world from one point-of-view and one point-of-view only: their own. It is, in other words, purely self-centered. Egocentric morality probably overlaps with Bronfenbrenner's self-oriented morality and at least with Kohlberg's reward-and-punishment stage.
The authoritarian view is a common one - perhaps the most common one. It is a step above the egocentric in that, although it is a subjective view, it takes into account the views of others. In fact, it may be said to absorb the views of others. Developmentally, the simple fact of living among other human beings leads one out of the egocentric into the authoritarian. The child must inevitably broaden his or her perspective to encompass that of significant others, if only to survive. In most circumstances, this process is enormously simplified by the fact that all of a child's immediate contacts share most of a single social reality.
This is the perspective that most fully accepts social
reality.
This means, however, that an authoritarian person accepts only one
social
reality, and understands it as universal. Someone who does
not
accept
the same social reality is seen as either an infant or
insane.
When
this social reality is threatened, either by another social
reality or
by
more immediate experiences, the tendency is for the person to
engage
their defensive mechanisms.
Most children, as well as the adults of primitive or isolated societies, or of highly structured traditional societies, will take this position. There is a tendency to legalistic thinking and an inordinate respect for tradition, even when that tradition is painful. Further, authoritarians tend to classify events, objects, and even people in pigeon-hole types or categories, with relatively few gradations. And they tend to believe in universal dualities - black vs white, good vs bad, us vs them... - with little room for in between or both.
I would divide the authoritarian perspective into four parts: The first part - call it the familial orientation - would be pretty close to Kohlberg's exchange stage plus good girl/good boy stage. The second part would be Bronfenbrenners three social types (authority-oriented, peer-oriented, and collective-oriented moralities).I am personally more interested in adult
forms of morality,
especially those that rise above the authoritarian perspective. So
instead of a single "post-conventional" or "objectively-oriented"
level, I postulate several:
First, there's the rationalistic
perspective. People with this
perspective value reason, words, logic. They seek an objective
truth
that they view as contained within the mind. When someone
who is
brought
up in one of the authoritarian traditions is exposed to other
social
realities beyond their own, they are most likely to seek
commonalities
among those traditions and develop ideal (and often idealistic)
structures to contain them, such as a moral system that extends
beyond
any one culture or society. Rationalistic morality is similar to
Kohlberg's stage of universal principles.
The cybernetic
perspective
is a synthesis of the
rationalistic
and the mechanistic. Instead, it accepts both reason and
empiricism as valid approaches to knowledge, and sees mind and
matter
as
two sides of the same coin. Instead of vast, ethereal
rationalistic theories, or cold, mathematical mechanistic
descriptions,
this perspective tends to try to model
reality - in words, or images,
or computer simulations.
The cybernetic view of morality is, as you might expect, an
interactive
one.
The impact of the valuer becomes important, and moral judgments
are
viewed
as having contexts. It is this view that I think better
accounts
for the highly moral women that Kohlberg's colleague, Carol
Gilligan,
wrote
about. These women, because they kept moral judgments in the
context
of social expectations, individual pains and pleasures, and so
forth,
were
judged by traditional Kohlberg standards as being of rather low
moral
development,
conventional (authoritarian) if not lower. Instead,
she
viewed these women as having a different approach to morality than
the
men, but at the same, or even higher, level. I agree with
Gilligan,
although I don't think this perspective is restricted to women.
Due to my life-long interest in phenomenology, existentialism,
and
Buddhist philosophy, I have come to the conclusion that there are
still
higher perspectives. They may be rare, but every once in a while,
one
comes across a person that seems special - a saint, we might say,
or a
bodhisattva. I have met a few, and read about a few more, as I
suspect
the
reader has as well. Here's my attempt at analyzing these people's
perspectives:
The lower version I call the intersubjective
perspective. As the name implies,
people in this perspective understand what I started this section
with:
That there is one reality and we all have different perspectives
on
that reality. And more: No one person can have a complete
understanding
of the one reality. It's just too big. So the best way to go about
understanding the universe - including ourselves - is to take a
good
look at all the various
ways
of looking at it - that is, being very open-minded
and tolerant - while always staying humble.
Of course, it isn't easy to be this way. For one thing, it's rather impractical. People in the lower perspectives make up their minds (or have their minds made up by others) and get down to the business of making the world fit their beliefs. But intersubjective people, after listening to hundreds of different opinions, can always be persuaded to listen to just one more! Plus, because they are so tolerant, they sometimes seem to pay too much attention to what others may think of as strange or even repulsive ideas. Most of us pay no attention to an ass - but the intersubjective person know that the ass is sometimes right!
The intersubjective perspective views moral value as necessarily
involving consciousness, yet having its own
reality. That is to say, good is to be found in the
interaction
of mind
and world, yet is not to be dismissed as therefore somehow unreal
-
especially
when you consider that all reality, to the extent that we have
anything
to do with it, is a matter of such interaction!
While it is true that the great majority of things that
distinguish
one person from another - or one culture from another - are just a
matter of habits or customs, there are, of course, some things
that are
of moral significance. The intersubjective perspective respects
the
variety of individuals and cultures, but does not shy away from
the
idea that some perspectives are, in fact, morally better than
others.
It recognizes that the good is a direction, not a place, and that
it is
real even though it cannot be expressed in the form of absolutes.
There is one more perspective I can see, even though I'd be the
first
to admit that I am not in it: the transcendental
perspective.
It is even more open, impractical, and, yes, flaky than the
intersubjective,
from the perspective of most of modern society, although primitive
and
traditional societies seem more accepting of it. It
involves,
as the name implies, transcending the multiple perspectives of the
intersubjective
and coming into direct contact with uninterpreted, immediate
reality. This is done
by
stripping away constructed reality altogether, through
techniques such as meditation.
This ultimately involves the diminution of desire and self. That means moving closer and closer to an unconscious state while retaining the ability to recall the experience. In a very real sense, it is a matter of dying - or almost dying - and returning to everyday reality with a new perspective on life.
Since eastern traditions have made quite an impact on the west in
the
last century or so, quite a number of words have become current as
labels
for this perspective: Tao, satori, moksha, buddhahood,
enlightenment,
nirvana,
cosmic consciousness, and so on. A good label is
Maslow's
peak experiences, in that
it
distances the phenomenon from particular
religious
practices and philosophical points of view, and especially
recognizes
that
the experience is one that normal people can have in their
everyday
lives,
not one only available to monks seated in the lotus position. It
describes any experience in which one loses one's sense of
individual
separateness
and feels instead a strong sense of union with all living things.
In the transcendental mode of morality, the good is an expression of one's intimacy with the universe, with the needs of all life, the desire of all consciousness. It is compassion.
The transcendental perspective is very suspicious of words. The
very
first
chapter
of the Tao te Ching, for example, warns us that the Tao that can
be
spoken isn't the true Tao. This said, I will take my own
advice
and cease to
discuss
the transcendental perspective. Or anything else, for that matter...
until the next chapter.