If a first magnitude has to a second the same ratio as a third has to a fourth, and the first is greater than the third, then the second is also greater than the fourth; if equal, equal; and if less, less. | ||
Let a first magnitude A have the same ratio to a second B as a third C has to a fourth D, and let A be greater than C.
I say that B is also greater than D. | ||
Since A is greater than C, and B is another, arbitrary, magnitude, therefore A has to B a greater ratio than C has to B. | V.8 | |
But A is to B as C is to D, therefore C has to D a greater ratio than C has to B. | V.13 | |
But that to which the same has a greater ratio is less, therefore D is less than B, so that B is greater than D. | V.10 | |
Similarly we can prove that, if A equals C, then B equals D, and, if A is less than C, then B is less than D. | ||
Therefore, if a first magnitude has to a second the same ratio as a third has to a fourth, and the first is greater than the third, then the second is also greater than the fourth; if equal, equal; and if less, less. | ||
Q.E.D. |
Another example comes from X.112.
Clearly, this proposition V.14 is not being invoked in either of these propositions, but the alternate form is used instead. That suggests that the proofs of VI.25 and X.112 were written when V.14 wasn't available.
The proof of the statement
Although this alternate form does not rely on using V.Def.4 as an axiom of comparability, the original form does. The statement of the proposition is false when infinitesimals are allowed. For a particular example, take the proportion x:(x + y) = x: (x + 2y) or its inverse.